A belief system is a set of mutually supportivebeliefs.
The beliefs of any such system can be classified as religious,
philosophical, political, ideological, or a combination of these.
Also Links as below
https://www.google.com/search?safe=strict&source=hp&q=belief
+system&oq=belief&gs_l=psy-ab.1.7.0i131k1l2j0j0i131k1j0l6.3060.
5467.0.24636.8.7.0.0.0.0.437.
1586.0j1j3j1j1.7.0....0...1.1.64.psy-ab..1.7.1797.6..35i39k1j0i20i264k1j0i131i46k1j46i131k1.211.T45-
Qjr0OC4
https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Belief
Belief
In epistemology, philosophers use the term "belief" to refer to personal attitudes associated with true or false ideas and concepts. However, "belief" does not require active introspection
and circumspection. For example, we never ponder whether or not
the sun will rise. We simply assume the sun will rise. Since "belief"
is an important aspect of mundane life, according to Eric Schwitzgebel
in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, a related question asks: "how a
physical
organism can have beliefs?"[3]
Knowledge and epistemology[edit]
Epistemology is concerned with delineating the boundary between
philosophical study of knowledge. The primary problem in epistemology
is to understand exactly what is needed in order for us to have knowledge.
In a notion derived from Plato's dialogue Theaetetus, where the
epistemology of Socrates (Platon) most clearly departs from that of
the sophists, who at the time of Plato seem to have defined knowledge
as what is here expressed as "justified true belief". The tendency to
translate from belief (here: doxa - common opinion) to knowledge
(here: episteme), which Plato (e.g. Socrates of the dialogue) utterly
dismisses, results from failing to distinguish a dispositive belief
(gr. 'doxa', not 'pistis') from knowledge (episteme) when the opinion is
regarded true (here: orthé), in terms of right, and juristically so
(according to the premises of the dialogue), which was the task of the
rhetors to prove. Plato dismisses this possibility of an affirmative relation
between belief (i.e. opinion) and knowledge even when the one who opines
grounds his belief on the rule, and is able to add justification (gr. logos:
reasonable and necessarily plausible assertions/evidence/guidance)
context of Theaetetus is not derived from the theological concept of belief,
which is pistis, but doxa, which in theological terms refers to acceptance
in the form of praise and glory.[citation needed]
Strangely, or not, Plato has been credited for the "justified true belief"
theory of knowledge, even though Plato in the Theaetetus (dialogue)
elegantly dismisses it, and even posits this argument of Socrates as a
cause for his death penalty . Among American epistemologists, Gettier (1963)[6] and Goldman (1967),[7] have
questioned the "justified true belief" definition, and challenged the
"sophists" of their time.
As a psychological phenomenon[edit]
Mainstream psychology and related disciplines have traditionally
treated belief as if it were the simplest form of mental representation
and therefore one of the building blocks of conscious thought. Philosophers
have tended to be more abstract in their analysis, and much of the work
examining the viability of the belief concept stems from philosophical analysis.
The concept of belief presumes a subject (the believer) and an object
of belief (the proposition). So, like other propositional attitudes,
belief implies the existence of mental states and intentionality, both of
which are hotly debated topics in the philosophy of mind, whose foundations
and relation to brain states are still controversial.
Beliefs are sometimes divided into core beliefs (that are actively thought about)
and dispositional beliefs (that may be ascribed to someone who has not
thought about the issue). For example, if asked "do you believe tigers wear
pink pajamas?" a person might answer that they do not, despite the fact
they may never have thought about this situation before.[8]
This has important implications for understanding the neuropsychology
and neuroscience of belief. If the concept of belief is incoherent, then any
attempt to find the underlying neural processes that support it will fail.
Philosopher Lynne Rudder Baker has outlined four main contemporary
approaches to belief in her controversial book Saving Belief:[9]
- Our common-sense understanding of belief is correct - Sometimes
- called the "mental sentence theory," in this conception, beliefs exist
- as coherent entities, and the way we talk about them in everyday life
- is a valid basis for scientific endeavour. Jerry Fodor is one of the principal
- defenders of this point of view.
- Our common-sense understanding of belief may not be entirely correct,
- but it is close enough to make some useful predictions - This view argues
- that we will eventually reject the idea of belief as we know it now, but that
- there may be a correlation between what we take to be a belief when
- someone says "I believe that snow is white" and how a future theory of
- psychology will explain this behaviour. Most notably, philosopher Stephen
- Stich has argued for this particular understanding of belief.
- Our common-sense understanding of belief is entirely wrong and will be
- completely superseded by a radically different theory that will have no
- use for the concept of belief as we know it - Known as eliminativism,
- this view (most notably proposed by Paul and Patricia Churchland)
- argues that the concept of belief is like obsolete theories of times
- past such as the four humours theory of medicine, or the
- phlogiston theory of combustion. In these cases science hasn't
- provided us with a more detailed account of these theories, but
- completely rejected them as valid scientific concepts to be replaced
- by entirely different accounts. The Churchlands argue that our
- common-sense concept of belief is similar in that as we discover
- more about neuroscience and the brain, the inevitable conclusion
- will be to reject the belief hypothesis in its entirety.
- Our common-sense understanding of belief is entirely wrong; however,
- treating people, animals, and even computers as if they had beliefs is
- often a successful strategy - The major proponents of this view,
- Daniel Dennett and Lynne Rudder Baker, are both eliminativists in that
- they hold that beliefs are not a scientifically valid concept, but they
- don't go as far as rejecting the
- concept of belief as a predictive device. Dennett gives the example
- of playing a computer at chess. While few people would agree that
- the computer held beliefs, treating the computer as if it did
- (e.g. that the computer believes that taking the opposition's queen
- will give it a considerable advantage) is likely to be a successful and
- predictive strategy. In this understanding of belief, named by Dennett
- the intentional stance, belief-based explanations of mind and behaviour
- are at a different level of explanation and are not reducible to those
- based on fundamental neuroscience, although both may be
- explanatory at their own level.
Strategic approaches make a distinction between rules, norms and
beliefs as follows: (1) Rules. Explicit regulative processes such as
policies, laws, inspection routines, or incentives. Rules function as a
coercive regulator of behavior and are dependent upon the imposing
entity’s ability to enforce them. (2) Norms. Regulative mechanisms
accepted by the social collective. Norms are enforced by normative
mechanisms within the organization and are not strictly dependent
upon law or regulation. (3) Beliefs. The collective perception of
fundamental truths governing behavior. The adherence to accepted
and shared beliefs by members of a social system will likely persist
and be difficult to change over time. Strong beliefs about determinant
factors (i.e., security, survival, or honor) are likely to cause a social
entity or group to accept rules and norms.[10]
Epistemological belief compared to religious belief
Historically belief-in belonged in the realm of religious thought, belief-that
instead belonged to epistemological considerations.[11]
Belief-in[edit]
To "believe in" someone or something is a distinct concept from "believing-that."
There are at least these types of belief-in:[12]
- Commendatory / Faith - we may make an expression of 'faith' in
- respect of some performance by an agent X, when without prejudice
- to the truth value of the factual outcome or even confidence in X
- otherwise, we expect that specific performance. In particular
- self-confidence or faith in one's self is this kind of belief.
- Existential claim - to claim belief in the existence of an entity
- or phenomenon in a general way with the implied need to justify
- its claim to existence. It is often used when the entity is not real,
- or its existence is in doubt. "He believes in witches and ghosts" or "
- many children believe in Santa Claus" or "I believe in a deity" are
- typical examples.[13] The linguistic form is distinct from the assertion
- of the truth of a proposition since verification is either considered
- impossible/irrelevant or a counterfactual situation is assumed.
Belief-that[edit]
Economical belief[edit]
Economic beliefs are beliefs which are reasonably and necessarily
contrary to the tenet of rational choice or instrumental rationality.[14]
Studies of the Austrian tradition of the economic thought, in the context
of analysis of the influence and subsequent degree of change resulting
from existing economic knowledge and belief, has contributed the
most to the subsequent holistic collective analysis.[15]
Delusion[edit]
Insofar as the truth of belief is expressed in sentential and propositional
form we are using the sense of belief-that rather than belief-in. Delusion
Delusions are defined as beliefs in psychiatric diagnostic criteria[19]
(for example in the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders).
Psychiatrist and historian G.E. Berrioshas challenged the view that delusions
are genuine beliefs and instead labels them as "empty speech acts,"
where affected persons are motivated to express false or bizarre belief
statements due to an underlying psychological disturbance. However,
the majority of mental health professionals and researchers treat delusions as if they were genuine beliefs.
"Why, sometimes I've believed as many as six impossible things before
breakfast." This is often quoted in mockery of the common ability of people
Formation[edit]
between beliefs and actions. Three models of belief formation and
change have been proposed:
The conditional inference process[edit]
When people are asked to estimate the likelihood that a
statement is true, they search their memory for information
that has implications for the validity of this statement. Once
this information has been identified, they estimate a) the likelihood
that the statement would be true if the information were true, and b)
the likelihood that the statement would be true if the information
were false. If their estimates for these two probabilities differ,
people average them, weighting each by the likelihood that the
information is true and false (respectively). Thus, information
bears directly on beliefs of another, related statement.[20]
Linear models of belief formation[edit]
Unlike the previous model, this one takes into consideration the possibility
of multiple factors influencing belief formation. Using regression procedures,
this model predicts belief formation on the basis of several different pieces
of information, with weights assigned to each piece on the basis of their
relative importance.[20]
Information processing models of belief formation
and change[edit]
These models address the fact that the responses people have to
belief-relevant information is unlikely to be predicted from the objective
basis of the information that they can recall at the time their beliefs are
reported. Instead, these responses reflect the number and meaning of
the thoughts that people have about the message at the time that they
encounter it.[20]
Some influences on people's belief formation include:
- Internalization of beliefs during childhood, which can form and shape
- our beliefs in different domains. Albert Einstein is often quoted as
- having said that "Common sense is the collection of prejudices acquired
- by age eighteen." Political beliefs depend most strongly on the political
- beliefs most common in the community where we live.[21] Most individuals
- believe the religion they were taught in childhood.[22]
- Charismatic leaders can form and/or modify beliefs (even if those beliefs
- fly in the face of all previous beliefs).[23] Is belief voluntary? Rational
- individuals need to reconcile their direct reality with any said belief;
- therefore, if belief is not present or possible, it reflects the fact that
- contradictions were necessarily overcome using cognitive dissonance.
- Advertising can form or change beliefs through repetition, shock, and
- association with images of sex, love, beauty, and other strong positive
- emotions.[24] Contrary to intuition, a delay, known as the sleeper effect,
- instead of immediate succession may increase an advertisement's ability
- to persuade viewer's beliefs if a discounting cue is present.[25]
- Physical trauma, especially to the head, can radically alter a person's beliefs.[26]
However, even educated people, well aware of the process by which beliefs
form, still strongly cling to their beliefs, and act on those beliefs even against
their own self-interest. In Anna Rowley's book, Leadership Therapy, she states
"You want your beliefs to change. It's proof that you are keeping your eyes
open, living fully, and welcoming everything that the world and people around
you can teach you." This means that peoples' beliefs should evolve as they
gain new experiences.[27]
Justified true belief[edit]
Justified true belief is a definition of knowledge that gained approval
during the Enlightenment, 'justified' standing in contrast to 'revealed'.
There have been attempts to trace it back to Plato and his dialogues
.[clarification needed][28] The concept of justified true belief states that in
order to know that a given proposition is true, one must not only believe
the relevant true proposition, but also have justification for doing so.
In more formal terms, an agent knows that a proposition is
true if and only if:
- is true
- believes that is true, and
- is justified in believing that is true
This theory of knowledge suffered a significant setback with the
discovery of Gettier problems, situations in which the above conditions
were seemingly met but that many philosophers disagree that anything
"justification" which he believed eliminates the problem: the justification
has to be such that were the justification false, the knowledge would be
false. Bernecker and Dretske (2000) argue that "no epistemologist since
Gettier has seriously and successfully defended the traditional view.".[30]:3
On the other hand, Paul Boghossian argues that the Justified True Belief
account is the "standard, widely accepted" definition of knowledge [31]
Modification[edit]
An extensive amount of scientific research and philosophical discussion
exists around the modification of beliefs, which is commonly referred
to as belief revision. Generally speaking, the process of belief revision
entails the believer weighing the set of truths and/or evidence, and the
dominance of a set of truths or evidence on an alternative to a held belief
can lead to revision. One process of belief revision is Bayesian updating
and is often referenced for its mathematical basis and conceptual simplicity.
However, such a process may not be representative for individuals
whose beliefs are not easily characterized as probabilistic.
There are several techniques for individuals or groups to change the
beliefs of others; these methods generally fall under the umbrella of
persuasion. Persuasion can take on more specific forms such as
consciousness raising when considered in an activist or political context.
Belief modification may also occur as a result of the experience of outcomes.
Because goals are based, in part on beliefs, the success or failure at a
particular goal may contribute to modification of beliefs that supported
the original goal.
Whether or not belief modification actually occurs is dependent not only
on the extent of truths or evidence for the alternative belief, but also
characteristics outside the specific truths or evidence. This includes,
but is not limited to: the source characteristics of the message, such as
credibility; social pressures; the anticipated consequences of a
modification; or the ability of the individual or group to act on the
modification. Therefore, individuals seeking to achieve belief
modification in themselves or others need to consider all possible
forms of resistance to belief revision.
Partial[edit]
Without qualification, "belief" normally implies a lack of doubt, especially
insofar as it is a designation of a life stance. In practical everyday use
however, belief is normally partial and retractable with varying degrees
of certainty.
A copious literature exists in multiple disciplines to accommodate this
other topics are largely directed to this.
Prediction[edit]
Different psychological models have tried to predict people's beliefs and
some of them try to estimate the exact probabilities of beliefs. For example,
people rate the likelihood of a certain statement (e.g., "It will rain tomorrow"),
this rating can be seen as a subjective probability value. The subjective
probability model posits that these subjective probabilities follow the
same rules as objective probabilities. For example, the law of total probability
might be applied to predict a subjective probability value. Wyer found that this
model produces relatively accurate predictions for probabilities of single events
and for changes in these probabilities, but that the probabilities of several beliefs
Religion[edit]
Religious belief refers to attitudes towards mythological,
belief is distinct from religious practice or religious behaviours
with some believers not practicing religion and some practitioners
not believing religion. Religious beliefs, being derived from ideas that
are exclusive to religion, often relate to the existence, characteristics
and human life, or the deontological explanations for the values and
practices centered on the teachings of a spiritual leader or group.
Forms of religious belief[edit]
While it is popularly conceived that religions each have identifiable and
exclusive sets of beliefs or creeds, surveys of religious belief have often
found that the official doctrine and descriptions of the beliefs offered by
religious authorities do not always agree with the privately held beliefs
of those who identify as members of a particular religion.[35] A broad
classification of the kinds of religious belief is documented below.
Fundamentalism[edit]
First self-applied as a term to the conservative doctrine outlined by
anti-modernist Protestants in the United States of America,[36]
fundamentalism as a religious belief is associated with a strict
adherence to an interpretation of scriptures that are generally
associated with theologically conservative positions or traditional
understandings of the text and are distrustful of innovative readings,
new revelation, or alternate interpretations. Religious fundamentalism
has been identified in the media as being associated with fanatical
or zealouspolitical movements around the world that have used a strict
adherence to a particular religious doctrine as a means to establish
political identity and enforce societal norms.
Orthodoxy[edit]
First used in the context of Early Christianity, orthodoxy is a religious
belief that closely follows the edicts, apologies, and hermeneutics of a
prevailing religious authority. In the case of Early Christianity, this authority
was the communion of bishops, and is often referred to by the term Magisterium.
The term orthodox was applied almost as an epithet to a group of Jewish
believers who held to pre-Enlightenment understanding of Judaism and
now known as Orthodox Judaism. The Eastern Orthodox Church of Christianity,
as well as the Catholic Church, consider themselves to be the true heir to
the Early Christian belief and practice. The antonym of orthodox is heterodox
and those adhering to orthodoxy often accuse the heterodox of apostasy,
Modernism/reform[edit]
The Renaissance and later the Enlightenment in Europe were associated
with varying degrees of religious tolerance and intolerance towards new
religious ideas. The Philosophestook particular exception to many of the
more fantastical claims of religions and directly challenged religious authority
and the prevailing beliefs associated with the established churches.
In response to the liberalizing political and social movements, some
religious groups attempted to integrate Enlightenment ideals of rationality,
equality, and individual liberty into their belief systems, especially into
the nineteenth and twentieth centuries. Reform Judaism and
Liberal Christianity are two examples of such religious associations.
Superstition[edit]
A term signifying derogation that is used by the religious and non-religious
alike, superstition is the deprecated belief in supernatural causation.
Those who deny the existence of the supernatural generally attribute all
beliefs associated with it to be superstitious while a typical religious critique
of superstition holds that it either encompasses beliefs in non-existent
supernatural activity or that the supernatural activity is inappropriately
paganism, and other folk religions were strongly condemned by
Christian Churches as mean forms of superstition, though such
condemnation did not necessarily eliminate the beliefs among the
common people and many such religious beliefs persist to today.
Systemization[edit]
In Buddhism, practice and progress along the spiritual path happens
when one follows the system of Buddhist practice. Any religion which
follows (parts of) the fundamentals of this system has, according to
the teachings of Buddha, good aspects to the extent it accords with this
system. Any religion which goes against (parts of) the fundamentals of
this system, includes bad aspects too. Any religion which does not teach
certain parts of this system, is not because of this a 'bad' religion; it just
lacks those teachings and is to that extent incomplete.
A question by the monk Subhadda to the Buddha:
(religious leaders) who are leaders of their sects, who arewell-esteemed by many people, such as Purana Kassapa,
Makkhali Gosala, Ajita Kesakambala, Pakudha Kaccayana,
Sancaya Belatthaputta and Nigantha Nataputta. Do all of them have knowledge and understanding as they themselves have declared? Or do all of them have no knowledge and understanding?"
The reply by Buddha was:
As a religious tradition, Hinduism has experienced many attempts
at systemization. In medieval times, Shankara advocated for the
Advaita system of philosophy. In recent times, Tamala Krishna
as expounded by Srila Prabhupada. (See Krishnology)
Universalism[edit]
Some believe that religion cannot be separated from other aspects of
life, or believe that certain cultures did not or do not separate their religious
activities from other activities in the same way that some people in
modern Western cultures do.
Some anthropologists[who?] report cultures in which gods are involved in
every aspect of life - if a cow goes dry, a god has caused this, and must be
propitiated, when the sun rises in the morning, a god has caused this, and
must be thanked. Even in modern Western cultures, many people see
supernatural forces behind every event, as described by Carl Saganin
his book The Demon-Haunted World.
People with this worldview often consider the influence of Western culture
to be inimical. Others with this world view resist the influence of science,
and believe that science, or "so-called science", should be guided by religion.
Still others with this worldview believe that all political decisions and laws
should be guided by religion. This last belief is written into the constitution
of many Islamic nations, and is shared by some fundamentalist Christians.
In addition, beliefs about the supernatural or metaphysical may not presuppose
a difference between any such thing as nature and non-nature, nor between
science and what the most educated people believe. In the view of some
culture and religion as not easily distinguishable, but all part of the same body of knowledge and wisdom available to a community.
Approaches to the beliefs of others[edit]
Adherents of particular religions deal with the differing doctrines and practices
espoused by other religions in a variety of ways. All strains of thought appear
in different segments of all major world religions.
Exclusivism[edit]
People with exclusivist beliefs typically explain other religions as either in error,
or as corruptions or counterfeits of the true faith. This approach is a fairly
consistent feature among smaller new religious movements that often rely
on doctrine that claims a unique revelation by the founder or leaders, and
consider it a matter of faith that the religion has a monopoly on truth.
All three major Abrahamic monotheistic religions have passages in their holy
scriptures that attest to the primacy of the scriptural testimony and indeed
monotheism itself is often couched as an innovation characterized specifically
by its explicit rejection of earlier polytheistic faiths.
Some exclusivist faiths incorporate a specific element of proselytization.
This is a strongly held belief in the Christian tradition which follows the
doctrine of the Great Commission, and is less emphasized by the
Islamic faith where the Quranic edict "There shall be no compulsion in
religion" (2:256) is often quoted as a justification for toleration of
alternative beliefs, while the Jewish tradition is one that does not
actively seek out converts.
Exclusivism correlates with conservative, fundamentalist, and
orthodox approaches of many religions while pluralistic and
syncretist approaches either explicitly downplay or reject the
exclusivist tendencies of the religion.
Inclusivism[edit]
People with inclusivist beliefs recognize some truth in all faith systems,
highlighting agreements and minimizing differences. The attitude is
sometimes associated with Interfaith dialogue or the
Christian Ecumenical movement, though in principle such attempts at
pluralism are not necessarily inclusivist and many actors in such
interactions (for example, the Roman Catholic Church) still hold to
exclusivist dogma while participating in inter-religious organizations.
Explicitly inclusivist religions include many that are associated with the
and Buddhism. The Bahá'í Faithconsiders it doctrine that there is truth
in all faith systems.
Pluralism[edit]
People with pluralist beliefs make no distinction between faith systems,
viewing each one as valid within a particular culture. Examples include:
- Extracts from the Sri Guru Granth Sahib Ji (Sikh Holy Scriptures),
- "There is only the One Supreme Lord God; there is no other at
- all" (Pannaa 45). "By His Power the Vedas and the Puranas exist,
- and the Holy Scriptures of the Jewish, Christian and Islamic religions.
- By His Power all deliberations exist." (Pannaa 464). "Some call Him,
- 'Ram, Ram', and some call Him, 'Khudaa-i'. Some serve Him as 'Gusain',
- others as 'Allaah'. ||1|| He is the Cause of causes, the Generous Lord.
- He showers His Grace and Mercy upon us amen." (Pannaa 885).
Syncretism[edit]
People with syncretistic views blend the views of a variety of different
religions or traditional beliefs into a unique fusion which suits their particular
experience and context (seeeclecticism). Unitarian Universalism is an
example of a syncretistic faith.
Adherence[edit]
Typical reasons for adherence to religion include:
- Belief in God is seen by some to be necessary for moral behavior.[37]
- Many people consider religious practices to be serene, beautiful,
- and conducive to religious experiences, which in turn support
- religious beliefs.[38]
- Organized religions promote a sense of community among their followers,
- and the moral and cultural common ground of these communities makes
- them attractive to people with the same values.[39] Indeed, while religious
- beliefs and practices are usually connected, some individuals with
- substantially secular beliefs still participate in religious practices
- for cultural reasons.
- Each religion asserts that it is a means by which its adherents may
- come into closer contact with God, Truth, and Spiritual Power. They all
- promise to free adherents from spiritual bondage, and bring them into
- spiritual freedom. It naturally follows that a religion which frees its
- adherents from deception, sin, and spiritual death will have significant
- mental health benefits. Abraham Maslow's research after World War II
- showed that Holocaust survivors tended to be those who held strong
- religious beliefs (not necessarily temple attendance, etc.), suggesting
- it helped people cope in extreme circumstances. Humanistic psychology
- went on to investigate how religious or spiritual identity may have correlations
- with longer lifespan and better health. The study found that humans may
- particularly need religious ideas to serve various emotional needs such as
- the need to feel loved, the need to belong to homogeneous groups, the
- need for understandable explanations and the need for a guarantee of
- ultimate justice. Other factors may involve sense of purpose, sense of identity,
- sense of contact with the divine. See also Man's Search for Meaning, by Victor
- Frankl, detailing his experience with the importance of religion in surviving the
- Holocaust. Critics assert that the very fact that religion was the primary selector
- for research subjects may have introduced a bias, and that the fact that all
- subjects were holocaust survivors may also have had an effect. According to
- Larson et al. (2000), "[m]ore longitudinal research with better multidimensional
- measures will help further clarify the roles of these [religious] factors and whether
- they are beneficial or harmful."[40]
Apostasy[edit]
Typical reasons for rejection of religion include:
- The fundamental doctrines of some religions are considered by some to be
- illogical, contrary to experience, or unsupported by sufficient evidence, and
- are rejected for those reasons.[41] Even some believers may have difficulty
- accepting particular religious assertions or doctrines. Some people believe
- the body of evidence available to humans to be insufficient to justify certain
- religious beliefs. They may thus disagree with religious interpretations of
- ethics and human purpose, or various creation myths. This reason has
- perhaps been aggravated by the protestations of some fundamentalist Christians.
- Some religions include beliefs that certain groups of people are inferior or
- sinful and deserve contempt, persecution, or even death, and that
- non-believers will be punished for their unbelief in an after-life.[42][43]
- Some people may be unable to accept the values that a specific religion
- promotes and will therefore not join that religion. They may also be unable
- to accept the proposition that those who do not believe will go to hell or be
- damned, especially if said nonbelievers are close to the person.
- The maintenance of life and the achievement of self-esteem require of a
- person the fullest exercise of reason—but morality, people are taught,
- rests on and requires faith.[44]
Systems[edit]
A belief system is a set of mutually supportive beliefs. The beliefs of any
or a combination of these. Philosopher Jonathan Glover says that beliefs
are always part of a belief system, and that tenanted belief systems are
Gilbert, sociological perspectives[edit]
A collective belief is referred to when people speak of what 'we' believe
when this is not simply elliptical for what 'we all' believe.
Sociologist Émile Durkheim wrote of collective beliefs and proposed that they,
like all 'social facts', 'inhered in' social groups as opposed to individual persons.
Durkheim's discussion of collective belief, though suggestive, is relatively obscure.
Philosopher Margaret Gilbert has offered a related account in terms of the
joint commitment of a number of persons to accept a certain belief as a body.
According to this account, individuals who together collectively believe
something need not personally believe it themselves. Gilbert's work on
the topic has stimulated a developing literature among philosophers.
One question that has arisen is whether and how philosophical accounts of
belief in general need to be sensitive to the possibility of collective belief.
Glover[edit]
Jonathan Glover believes that he and other philosophers ought to play some
role in starting dialogues between people with deeply held, opposing beliefs,
especially if there is risk of violence. Glover also believes that philosophy
can offer insights about beliefs that would be relevant to such dialogue.
Glover suggests that beliefs have to be considered holistically, and that no belief exists in isolation in the mind of the believer. It always implicates and relates to other beliefs.[45] Glover provides the example of a patient with an illness who
returns to a doctor, but the doctor says that the prescribed medicine is
not working. At that point, the patient has a great deal of flexibility
in choosing what beliefs to keep or reject: the patient could believe
that the doctor is incompetent, that the doctor's assistants made a mistake,
that the patient's own body is unique in some unexpected way, that
Western medicine is ineffective, or even that Western science is entirely
unable to discover truths about ailments.[45]
Glover maintains that any person can continue to hold any belief if they
would really like to[45] (e.g., with help from ad hoc hypotheses).
One belief can be held fixed, and other beliefs will be altered around it.
Glover warns that some beliefs may not be entirely explicitlybelieved
(e.g., some people may not realize they have racist belief systems
adopted from their environment as a child). Glover believes that people
tend to first realize that beliefs can change, and may be contingent on their
upbringing, around age 12 or 15.[45]
Glover emphasizes that beliefs are difficult to change. He says that
one may
try to rebuild one's beliefs on more secure foundations (axioms), like building
a new house, but warns that this may not be possible. Glover offers the
example of René Descartes, saying about Descartes that "[h]e starts off
with the characteristic beliefs of a 17th-century Frenchman; he then junks
the lot, he rebuilds the system, and somehow it looks a lot like the beliefs
of a 17th-century Frenchman." To Glover, belief systems are not like
houses but are instead like boats. As Glover puts it: "Maybe the whole
thing needs rebuilding, but inevitably at any point you have to keep
enough of it intact to keep floating."[45]
Glover's final message is that if people talk about their beliefs, they
may find more deep, relevant, philosophical ways in which they disagree
(e.g., less obvious beliefs, or more deeply held beliefs). Glover thinks that
people often manage to find agreements and consensus through philosophy.
He says that at the very least, if people do not convert each other, they
will hold their own beliefs more openmindedly and will be less likely
Law[edit]
The British philosopher Stephen Law has described some belief systems
"claptrap" and said that they "draw people in and hold them captive so
they become willing slaves to victory... if you get sucked in, it can be
extremely difficult to think your way clear again".[48]
See also[edit]
- Alief
- Collective behavior
- Culture-specific syndrome
- Doxastic attitudes
- Doxastic logic
- Expectation (epistemic)
- Folk psychology
- Idea
- Moore's paradox
- Nocebo
- Observer-expectancy effect
- Opinion
- Placebo
- Propositional knowledge
- Psychosomatic illness
- Self-deception
- Spell (paranormal)
- Spirituality
- Subject-expectancy effect
- Subjective validation
- Sugar pill
- Suggestibility
- Suggestion
- Theory of justification
- Thomas theorem
- Trust
- Unintended consequence
- Validity
- Value (personal and cultural)
- World view
No comments:
Post a Comment